Liking, disliking, and averaging: Why average things are attractive but very attractive things are not average

By Gordon Rugg and Amy Martin

There are regularities in human desire. Often, though, the actual regularities are subtly but profoundly different from the apparent regularities.

In this article, we’ll look at one of these regularities. It starts with a significant insight from an article whose title neatly sums up a key finding, and implicitly raises a key question.

The article is a 1996 paper by Rhodes and Tremewan in Psychological Science. The title is: “Average faces are attractive, but very attractive faces are not average.” The implicit question is: “Why?”

There’s been a lot of work in this area. In this article, we’ll examine how a simple change in the way you represent the data can give powerful new insights into what’s actually going on, and into what you can do about it.

Historical background

In this article, we’ll mainly use faces as the subject matter for perceptions of attractiveness, because of the amount of good work in this area.

The technique of averaging faces by superimposing photographs of different faces has been around for a long time. The first examples date from the 1870s.

It was swiftly noticed that averaged faces are usually perceived as attractive; in fact, they’re often perceived as more attractive than any of the individual faces that went into the average. Similarly, individual faces which are similar to the photographically averaged faces (“average” or “prototypical” as opposed to “averaged” faces) are also typically perceived as attractive.

There has been considerable research into this, broadly dividing into two strands, namely the evolutionary strand, which emphasises symmetry and prototypicality as an honest signal of reproductive fitness, and the cognitive strand, which emphasises the lower cognitive processing load associated with symmetrical and prototypical stimuli. There’s a reasonable overview on Wikipedia.

Representations of attractiveness and unattractiveness

One point which has been repeatedly raised about photographically averaged faces is that the averaging process produces a face which doesn’t have facial blemishes. This explains some of the apparent paradox in the Rhodes and Tremewan title, but doesn’t really address the part about very attractive faces.

The apparent paradox makes more sense if you tackle the question from a different direction, by treating attractiveness and unattractiveness as two separate dimensions, rather than as opposite ends of a single scale.

Here’s a hypothetical example, where the black circles represent faces, the vertical (light green) axis represents attractiveness, and the horizontal (red) axis shows unattractiveness. The circles are loosely clustered around the centre of the plot. One circle towards the top left has been rated as above average in attractiveness, and low in unattractiveness; another, towards the top right, has been rated as fairly high both in attractiveness and unattractiveness.

Suppose that we now remove facial blemishes from the photos, and have them re-rated. The removal of blemishes reduces the bad points of the photos, but doesn’t add any significant new attractive features. This shifts the values to the left (reduced unattractiveness, but no increase in attractiveness).

This is exactly what happens in software interface design when you remove the bugs from an early design; the “dislike” ratings decrease, but you need to add something new to make the “like” ratings increase. Removing bad features isn’t the same as adding good features.

In the context of product design, you can add good features by using input from the previous evaluation sessions, or by using idea generation methods. You aim for an end point like the one below, where the ratings are all high on liking and low on disliking.

This raises some interesting questions about whether attractiveness is in some way different from the average. We’ll return to these questions near the end of this article.

High attractiveness

So what makes something very attractive? We argue that there are two important issues. One involves perceived threat; the other involves novelty. In brief, non-threatening novelty is good; threat is bad; non-novelty is bad. However, deciding whether or not something is threatening can be difficult, and this issue has its own role in attractiveness.

Threat, and the uncanny valley

One key issue is whether something is perceived as potentially threatening or not. As soon as a real threat is involved, there’s a separate dynamic, and attractiveness ceases to be a significant issue.

The word “perceived” is important. An obvious issue is that what would be threatening to one person would not be threatening to another. Less obviously, uncertainty about whether or not there is a real threat has far-reaching regularities in terms of human behaviour.

The phenomenon of the uncanny valley is widely known. It occurs when something or someone is neither clearly human nor clearly non-human. Many classic monsters are of this type, and not just because they’re easy to handle in special effects; werewolves and vampires were in the uncanny valley long before films began. Similarly, there’s a well-recognised risk that attempting to improve an image of a face by filtering out the blemishes may backfire by turning the image into something doll-like in the uncanny valley.

The literature on the uncanny valley tends to assume that this effect only applies to uncertainty about whether or not something is human. Gordon has previously argued here and here that the uncanny valley is just one example of a broader phenomenon, involving uncertainty about potential threat.

In brief, a situation can unfold in four main ways, in terms of threat. If it begins looking harmless, and then flips to being scary, that produces horror. Conversely, if it begins looking scary, and then flips to being harmless, that produces humour.

This model has the advantage of bringing together humour and horror into a single framework. It also makes sense of phenomena such as trompe-l’oeil images, which begin by looking like one type of harmless image, and then flip into a different harmless image. We’ll return to this issue later, in regard to novelty.

Reducing perceived threat

There are various ways of reducing threat, with regard to perceived human attractiveness.

One route which has received a lot of attention is infantilisation of women; a related route is impractical clothing and footwear for women. An underlying assumption here is that males are threatening. A related issue is that many people use a rigid binary categorisation into male and female, and feel threatened when that categorisation is challenged by e.g. clothing that doesn’t fit neatly into the two categories of “male clothing” and “female clothing”. This is a fascinating topic, but would take us outside the scope of this article.

Another variable which affects perceived threat and perceived attractiveness involves features which are associated with group membership. In the everyday world, this can involve choice of hairstyle, cosmetics, etc, but can also involve features which are more difficult to modify, such as hair colour, eye colour and skin colour.

Researchers into facial attractiveness usually eliminate this variable as far as possible by using photos of faces without cosmetics, jewellery, visible hair, etc, and by using photos which standardise as far as possible for skin colour, eye colour, etc. However, it’s not possible to eliminate completely all the potential signals of group membership which might affect perceptions of attractiveness. We’ll return to group membership later in this article.

So, potential threat is an issue in attractiveness; in the next section we’ll look at how this interacts with the issue of novelty.

Novelty and desire

It’s trivially obvious that people enjoy non-threatening novelty. It’s less obvious how much novelty someone will want, or when they will want it, and what form it should take. In the next sections, we’ll look at ways of answering these and other questions about novelty.

Novelty, and sensory diet

There are various ways of measuring novelty. They usually involve treating novelty as the inverse of frequency. For instance, if you’ve heard ten thousand tunes which feature guitars, and only ten tunes which feature mandolins, then the novelty value of a new tune featuring mandolins will be a thousand times higher than the novelty value of a new tune featuring guitars.

One tempting conclusion to draw is that people each have their own preferred “sweet spot” for novelty. The reality is almost certainly more complicated. If you investigate how people use music, for example, there’s a strong tendency to use different types of music for different purposes, such as low-novelty music as “wallpaper” when concentrating on a difficult task, and high-novelty music as a “foreground” when listening to music for pleasure.

If you look at novelty across different sensory channels, you also get a strong impression that people’s preferences for novelty make more sense across an extended timescale of days or weeks or longer. What seems to be going on involves periods of moderate novelty interspersed with episodes of higher novelty. There appears to be a similar pattern for arousal levels.

Gordon has previously blogged here about how this can be viewed in terms of sensory diet and sensory self-regulation. The figure below shows a hypothetical plot for one sense across time, with ten time points, varying around a central average.

A hypothetical sensory diet, showing sensory load versus time for one sense

This raises obvious questions about which senses are involved. Human beings have significantly more than the five traditionally recognised senses (sight, hearing, taste, smell and touch). They also have senses such as proprioception, which tells you where each part of your body is even when you can’t see it. Depending on the definition you use, there are somewhere between a dozen and twenty senses (for instance, there seem to be different sensory pathways involved in light touch and in firm touch).

When you start looking at the full sensory package in terms of sensory diet, you start to see the sport/recreation/entertainment industry in a very different way.

Also, interestingly, you start to see relationships to social issues that are usually viewed as belonging to completely different categories. For instance, if you use the same framework of full sensory package and sensory diet, you start perceiving antisocial and marginalised activities in a very different light. You start asking questions about the role of sensory self-regulation in joyriding or drug use or graffiti, and whether this framework might provide a constructive way of tackling these issues. It’s a fascinating topic, but it goes beyond the scope of this article, so we won’t explore it further here.

Information content and novelty; the beauty 2 SDs from the mean

There’s been a fair amount of research into the mathematical regularities that underly perceptions of beauty. An excellent paper by Ramachandran & Hirstein outlined a radically new model of art based on this approach. Unsurprisingly, it was not exactly welcomed with open arms by the established art community, but its content has stood up well to the test of time.

One particularly robust regularity is the mathematical location of aesthetic sweet spots. A simple example in lay language is that being tall or petite is generally perceived as attractive, but being very tall or very petite is not.

More rigorously stated, the sweet spot typically occurs about 1.5 to 2 standard deviations from the mean. Below this point, things are perceived as ordinary; above it, they’re perceived as freakish.

Our phrasing about “generally and “typically” reflects the way that individuals vary in their preferences; the figure of 1.5 to 2 standard deviations is a typical figure, not an invariant law. Gordon has previously blogged here and here about situations where this tendency can be over-ridden by other factors, such as competitiveness for most extreme values. On the whole, though, it’s a solid principle, which hasn’t received the attention that it deserves.

Non-threatening puzzle solving and parsing

Returning briefly to non-threatening puzzle solving, passtimes such as crosswords and Sudoku make sense as a source of non-threatening novelty.

They also make sense in terms of a concept from the humour literature, which is the sense of pleasant relief when an ambiguous situation is disambiguated in a non-threatening way. This is a standard part of the cognitive model of humour. It probably also applies in a milder form to puzzles where there are multiple candidate solutions, and where the solution identifies the correct solution.

Some situations are non-threatening, but don’t have single unambiguous solutions. Gordon has blogged here about non-threatening Necker shifts in design, such as trompe-l’oeil designs, and here about how some types of abstract art can be viewed as part of the same phenomenon.

In summary, then:

  • Threat and novelty are two important variables in human desire
  • Novelty can be measured in various ways, giving more rigorous insights into the underlying regularities in human desire.

Conclusion and implications

Beauty, ugliness, and Cara Delevingne’s eyebrows

An approach that we often use is to take a pair of concepts that are usually viewed as opposite ends of a single scale, and then see what happens if we treat them as two separate scales.

If we do this with attractiveness and ugliness, the result makes sense of already existing concepts in aesthetics. The figure below shows how existing concepts fit onto this space.

The concept of “belle laide” (also known as “jolie laide”) in the top right corner involves someone being unconventionally attractive. A striking example is Cara Delevingne’s much-admired eyebrows, which were very different from the previously prevalent view that female eyebrows should be slim. There’s an excellent example of her eyebrows in action here.

The beautiful people, the ugly people, and the others

The issue of distance from the mean raises some interesting questions about group identity and beautiful people. People who are very far from the mean are typically perceived as freakish and/or in the uncanny valley. What, though, about people in the sweet spot of about 2 standard deviations from the mean? Are they perceived as belonging to a group of beautiful people different from ordinary people?

The short answer is that we don’t know. It’s plausible, and there’s anecdotal evidence that supports this idea, but we don’t know.

So, in summary:

  • The finding that average faces are attractive, but very attractive faces are not average, is not a paradox if you treat attractiveness and ugliness as two separate dimensions.
  • Removing blemishes will make a face less unattractive.
  • A very attractive face is likely to be about two standard deviations from the mean in some key variable.
  • What is true of facial attractiveness is also true of many other areas of human desire. Many, but not all…

We’ll explore related concepts in later articles.

Notes and links

Original article reference:

Rhodes, G., & Tremewan, T. (1996). Average faces are attractive, but very attractive faces are not average. Psychological Science, 7, 105-110.

Previous articles on this blog about the mathematics of desire

https://hydeandrugg.wordpress.com/2014/08/28/the-mathematics-of-desire/

https://hydeandrugg.wordpress.com/2015/03/28/people-in-architectural-drawings-part-2-the-mathematics-of-desire/

 

You’re welcome to use Hyde & Rugg copyleft images for any non-commercial purpose, including lectures, provided that you state that they’re copyleft Hyde & Rugg.

There’s more about the theory behind this article in my book Blind Spot, by Gordon Rugg with Joseph D’Agnese:

http://www.amazon.co.uk/Blind-Spot-Gordon-Rugg/dp/0062097903

You might also find our website useful:

http://www.hydeandrugg.com/

Related articles:

Overviews of the articles on this blog:

https://hydeandrugg.wordpress.com/2015/01/12/the-knowledge-modelling-book/

https://hydeandrugg.wordpress.com/2015/07/24/200-posts-and-counting/

https://hydeandrugg.wordpress.com/2014/09/19/150-posts-and-counting/

https://hydeandrugg.wordpress.com/2014/04/28/one-hundred-hyde-rugg-articles-and-the-verifier-framework/

 

1 thought on “Liking, disliking, and averaging: Why average things are attractive but very attractive things are not average

  1. Pingback: Games people play, and their implications | hyde and rugg

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google photo

You are commenting using your Google account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.